October
6, 2015
Written by Maximus Peperkamp, M.S.
Verbal Engineer
Dear Reader,
This
writing is my tenth response to “The Unit of Selection: What Do Reinforcers
Reinforce?” by J.W. Donahoe, D.C. Palmer and J.E. Burgos (1997). I am, of course, in agreement with these authors
behaviorist’ premise: “We believe that we are justified in considering covert
events
. . . in our interpretation
of complex behavior provided that we do not introduce ad hoc principles that
are not founded in the experimental
analysis of overt,
measurable, quantifiable behavior. . . . Inferences about covert events should follow from
behavioral
laws, not serve to
mask their inadequacy. (LCB, pp.
275–277).” As I have stated, Sound Verbal Behavior (SVB) covert speech is a
function of SVB public speech. Likewise, Noxious Verbal Behavior (NVB) private
speech is a function of NVB public speech. It can’t be otherwise; what we say
to ourselves is determined by how we have talked with others. If others talk at us, we will be talking at ourselves, but if others are talking with us, we will we be talking with ourselves. In talking at each other and at ourselves there is always a separation between the speaker and
the listener, but in talking with
each other and talking with ourselves
the speaker and the listener are experienced as one. Like these authors, I am also
not much interested in “ad hoc principles that are not founded in
the experimental analysis of overt, measurable, quantifiable behavior.”
The listener’s auditory
distinction between the speaker’s public speech, SVB or NVB is not an inference
of the listener’s covert event, but is based on the lawfulness of overt
behavioral laws. However, it should be clear to the reader that these verbal
response classes are quantifiable only by means of conversation and cannot be measured
while we are only involved in reading and writing. Analysis of SVB and NVB
makes no sense in written form. Our demand for this written form represents our
bias toward visual stimuli. These words and sentences are visible, but they
have no sound.
The authors mention “four
reasons for integrating the experimental analysis of behavior and
neuroscience”, and insist “that distinctions
between different levels of
analysis—or, better perhaps, different scales of measurement (Philip Hineline,
personal communication)—are epistemological, not ontological. That is, the
distinction is between
different ways of studying
the same nature, not different natures.” Yet, they don’t consider talking as
one of those “different ways of studying the same nature.” Their NVB way of
talking doesn’t permit it and they have no idea that another way of talking, SVB,
would. Not surprisingly, they remain busy with “observations at finer
levels of analysis, whether microbehavioral or neural” (underlining added by
me). Even at these neuroscientific “finer levels of analysis” their visual bias
continues, but in real conversation (SVB) “finer levels of analysis” involves
listening.
These scholars worry about “Some
antecedent–behavior relations” that seem to “exemplify nonlinearly separable
functions—such as the XOR problem in artificial intelligence (viz., Hutchison)—that
require the introduction of mediating events if ad hoc formulations are to be
avoided”, but they don’t mention anything about the affect-inducing speaker.
Moreover, since the listener, who, as we all know, mediates the speaker, is
either positively or negatively affected by the speaker’s voice and in
principle can talk about that, since the speaker-as-own-listener bridges the
environment within and outside of the skin, there is really no reason for the
“introduction of mediating events.” If these authors are “motivated by a simple
curiosity about the processes underlying the functional
relations between the environment and behavior’’, why don’t they acknowledge the
simple fact that they, like everyone else who learned a language, are affected
by auditory stimuli?
In NVB the speaker is not
aware of how he or she sounds while he or she speaks. Consequently, he or she
forces others to listen to him or her. In SVB, the speaker listens to him or
herself while he or she speaks. Thus, in
SVB, the speaker is not aversively stimulating the listener. The listener, who
can be the speaker, listens effortlessly to the SVB speaker.
Although Skinner wrote Verbal
Behavior (1957), he also remained unaware of the SVB/NVB distinction and gave
priority to visual stimuli. Had he known this distinction, he would never made
the statement: “The physiologist of the future will tell us all that can be
known about what is happening inside the behaving organism. His account will be
an important advance over a behavioral analysis, because the latter is
necessarily ‘‘historical’’— that is to say, it is confined to functional relations
showing temporal gaps. . . .What he discovers cannot invalidate the laws
of a science of behavior, but it will make the picture of human action
more nearly complete (Skinner, 1974, pp. 236–237).” To “tell us all that can be
known about what is happening inside” the physiologist would still have to
achieve SVB, but as long as he or she engages in NVB, he or she will be biased.
Remarkably, Skinner considers behavioral analysis as “necessarily historical –
that is to say, it is confined to functional relations showing temporal gaps.” Anyone
who has explored SVB knows that such a statement derives from NVB. The
functional relations that bring forth SVB can immediately be explored, verified
and agreed upon, by talking. In SVB the
speaker’s immediate positive impact on the listener is tangible and the speaker
and the listener are conscious. In NVB, by contrast, there is no way in which
the impact of the speaker on the listener can be addressed. Therefore, in SVB these
“temporal gaps” don’t even occur. I
disagree with Skinner that the physiologist’s account “will make the picture
of human action more nearly complete” (underlining added by me). There is
no picture or puzzle to be completed, but there is definitely a way of talking
in which we don’t listen as what we say is presumably more important than how
we say it. Only if NVB is recognized as such can it be stopped. When NVB is
stopped we will have SVB. It is necessary for NVB to be addressed first, before
we can have SVB. Therefore, the speaker’s voice in NVB is called Voice 1 and
the speaker’s voice in SVB is called Voice 2.
“Temporal gaps” in the behavioral account of human interaction come down
to missing frequencies in the production as well as the reception of sound. Sounds
which we don’t produce, we also don’t tend to hear.
No comments:
Post a Comment